I concluded my last post by
saying that, within the context of evangelization my problem, as a literary
artist, is whether and how it is possible to create a Hero, and indeed a Saint,
who is neither a rogue, nor a naïve, nor a bore. Obviously the only satisfactory answer to
this problem is to produce a performance which can be judged on its
merits. But it seems worthwhile to
sketch out some reasons, theoretically speaking, for why the performance ought
not to be considered fruitless on the face of it.
Typically, the reason given for
disliking noble characters—be they saints in the strict sense, or simply that
flavor of unblemished cowboy, superhero, or soldier whom the critics tend to
despise—is that they are boring. There
is no interior conflict, or no real conflict, in such characters; they are, we
are told, unrelatable. Superman and
Captain America are bland compared to Batman and Iron Man.
And there is a certain amount
of truth in that criticism. We literary
artists tend to present noble men blandly—and, I would argue, badly—in the
sense that a bland presentation of a noble man is, in fact, an inaccurate
presentation. The comment on my previous
post suggested that this is perhaps because “nemo dat quod non got” (my preferred presentation of the adage):
the artist cannot portray what he does not have or know. Artists do not know what it is like to be
noble, not because they are particularly bad men, but because few men in general
are noble; having few examples of nobility around them, artists have difficulty
in portraying nobility. The unswerving
exterior of a noble man—for it appears unswerving and unclouded from a distance—becomes
for these distance-artists a key to his interior character. The inner
debate which ordinary selfish human beings experience, the should-I-shouldn’t-I,
is removed from the representation of noble man’s psyche, and nothing is put in
to replace it. The noble man is empty or
at best filled with a single-minded and undynamic interest in the pursuit of a severe
ideal. He is “too good” to be tempted
from the ideal; but too good looks to most of us to be only too cold.
In some sense this portrait is
correct. The good man is unswerving in his devotion of the
ideal; thinkers from Aristotle onwards have understood that true virtue entails
such a love of the good as to reduce temptations from the interior to a
negligible minimum ( barring special cases of testing, through which God will
sometimes put his favorites).
Our Lady is the paradigmatic
example of this nobility: “full of grace” by the gift of God, she was not
subject to the struggles native to fallen human nature. In fact, if Aristotle’s magnanimous man is
not incompatible with the Christian ideal, one might say that Our Lady is the
only truly magnanimous being to ever walk the earth.
“Magnificat anima mea
Dominum …”
If she experienced sorrow or
some sense of conflict, it was not due to her sin or imperfection, but to the sins
and imperfections of others. And lest
this other-directed sorrow sound overbearing or holier-than thou, I submit the
parallel case of a child, learning for the first time of some grownup
failing. We do not look the innocent in
the eye and suppose that we are being judged—or, if we are being judged, we
know it is only because we richly deserve it.
So, I would imagine, with Our Lady: not that she is ignorant, as the
child is, but innocent, not knowing good an evil with that unfortunate intimacy
which is part and parcel of daily existence for the rest of us.
If, then, Our Lady experienced
some sort of internal conflict, it will not be from temptations rooted in her
own soul—and likewise, the noble man qua
noble will not be self-tempted. I do not
say noble men are never self-tempted—of course they are; no one is perfect in
the way that Our Lady is. But the whole
question of this series is whether perfection can be portrayed in an appealing
way; and hence it is the noble man on a good day, as it were, who concerns us
here.
But even if his own
imperfection is ruled out as a source of interior interest, there are three conceivable
sources of interior conflict left to the good man: temptations from the
exterior, sorrow at the sins of others, and intellectual doubts. The first, what I am calling “temptations
from the exterior,” is better known under the name “the dark night of the soul”—and
while it certainly belongs to the experience of many saints, it suffers from
the same flaw, artistically, as self-temptation: it is a deeply felt temptation to sin, albeit one for which the saint is
not blamed. It is an imperfection, not
natural but supernatural in origin; a test, and a glorious one for those who,
from St. Paul to Mother Theresa, succeed in passing it. But however glorious the flaw, a flaw it is—and
thus once again inadmissible in light of the original problem.
The literary artist desirous of
portraying perfection is left, then, with two kinds of conflict in the soul of
the noble man: sorrow at the sins of others, and intellectual doubts. I would argue that both interior tendencies
provide potentially fruitful sources of conflict for the literary artist—but more
of that to come.
2 comments:
Oh! Let me highlight an important variant of the first "solution": in a Convert, sorrow for his own past sins.
Yes! Which would be a step away from the self-tortured model.
Post a Comment