Perhaps it is the election cycle,
perhaps the increased intensity of my own research—whatever the cause, I’ve
become far more aware over the past few months of the amount of anger in
academia.
I’m not referring to the anger of
students, to the
dangerous absurdities that most often make the news, but to the anger of
the academics themselves. It is,
fortunately, not nearly so universal a trait as (to choose a quality at random)
the habit of carrying one’s own dry-erase markers; but it is common enough to
be noticeable—remarkable, in the etymological sense of the word—especially in
the humanities.
All professors in the humanities
are inclined, by profession as it were, to make professions—indeed, to commit
what are referred to coyly in the Catholic world as “professions of faith.” As with all good faiths, these professions
involve negative and positive elements.
A Catholic rejects sin and Satan, and embraces Jesus Christ; a biologist
rejects cancer, and embraces health. The
Catholic may study sin (indeed, a great many of us are walking human experiments
in the subject, making it well-nigh
irresistible for the eager student), but that hardly suggests that the Catholic
is in favor of sinning. Likewise, the
biologist may study cancer, but only with the purpose of contributing to its
eventual eradication. His focus, like
the peccatologist’s, may be on the evil he sees all around him; but the evil is
evil precisely because it is destroying some good. His anger may be severe, but it is an anger
ultimately based on love of something beautiful.
The oddity in the humanities is
that this does not always appear to be the case. Within literature in particular, there are
certain scholars who seem to take delight in studying things which make them
angry, things which on some level they regard as evil—but with no apparent
consciousness of the good or the beautiful in the background. They are professors whose profession appears
to be fundamentally negative.
Chinua Achebe’s famous
essay on Joseph Conrad’s The Heart of
Darkness is a classic instance of the phenomenon. Achebe’s argument, in brief, is that Conrad’s
portrayal of Africans makes them the real dark centers of the story. For decades readers focused on Kurtz’s
corruption and the irony that of corruption, given the purportedly “civilizing”
influence of Europeans in Africa; and finding in the story, if anything, a
lesson against supposing that one’s race or culture is a guarantor of one’s
virtue. But Achebe argues that, despite
the superficial appearance of cultural humility, Conrad’s work is essentially culturally
imperialistic, inasmuch as it highlights the superiority of European culture to
African again and again.
A counter reading of the novella might
emphasize the role of the narrator, his prejudices and his disenchantment, more
than Achebe does. But be that as it may,
Achebe is correct to observe that the portrayal of Africans in the story
displays prejudice. And given the
correctness of his observation, there is nothing surprising about his anger. Nor is it surprising that he should write an
entire lecture fueled by that anger.
It is not even surprising that his
is not the only scholastic effort bent on tearing to shreds a previously
well-accepted piece of literature. If
artists can be prejudiced like anyone else, they are capable of writing things
that are offensive; and naturally, if everyone goes around lauding such works
to the skies for their artistic merit without noticing that there is offense in
them, the situation ought to be rectified. I, personally, have always found Ulysses offensive, and (if I ever get
around to actually reading it) may someday write a scathingly brilliant essay
against it myself.
But I doubt I will ever actually
write the essay. For one thing, Ulysses is a very long book, and I have
plenty of other things left to read. There
are so many good books that it seems a waste of time to gorge on one which
(based on the excerpts I’ve encountered and the descriptions I have read) would
be profoundly antithetical not only to my aesthetic taste but also to my moral principles. A work of genius I have no doubt it is. But again, there are even so many works of
genius in existence that it is probably more worth my time to read Moby Dick (for example) than Joyce’s equally
oversized saga.
(I know, I know—it’s scandalous
that an English PhD student
hasn’t read Moby Dick. I didn’t get around to Crime and Punishment
or Anna Karenina until a couple years ago. And I still haven’t read
Timon
of Athens. Consider this my Lenten
abasement for the week.)
The world is so full of a number
of things (observed Stevenson), I’m sure we should all be as happy as
kings. There’s no reason to spend time
on books that one doesn’t enjoy. And
there’s certainly no reason to make them the focus of one’s academic
career. And yet, people do. People do dedicate their academic careers—not
simply to works by men who are flawed (all of us are); nor even to works that
themselves show the dark side of the era in which they were written (few, I suspect,
do not); but to works that they consider the embodiment of everything that they
don’t like about literature.
Now there is a way in which this
approach is similar to that of the biologist with cancer. The biologist wants healthy people, and
therefore he focuses on eradicating a disease that kills billions of them. In the same way, perhaps, the feminist literary
scholar who despises pre-modern portrayals of women is certainly a proponent of
women, and of their accurate portrayals. But literature does not work like medicine, or
even like philosophy. In medicine, if enough
people study a bug for a long enough time, the bug generally gets licked. Even in philosophy, the theory is (or was)
that if enough people argue about a bad philosopher for a long enough time, his
errors will become apparent and his influence, therefore, will be destroyed. In literature, however, the more people study
a work—even a morally questionable work—the more of a life the work seems to
have. One does not kill prejudice by
angry academic writing; one perpetuates it by extending its voice.
The real solution, if a work is
sufficiently morally iniquitous to make one angry, is to ignore it and to study
or write something else, something more morally worthy of attention. Scholars here could stand to learn a
practical lesson from politics: giving air time to an opponent is usually a
strategic mistake. But scholars, like
politicians and people in general, sometimes let their anger get the better of
them, and spend endless reservoirs of time and effort and influence trying to dismantle
a canon they perceive as problematic and, in the process, reminding the
rest of us of its existence. Wiser would
be the man (however wrong) to argue that Samson Agonistes is a work of terrorist
literature, and leave it at that.
But the real oddity of the angry
literary scholar is not even his impracticality—scholars are, after all,
stereotypically bad at realizing how their ideas will affect those around them.
(For example.)
No, the real oddity of the angry
literary scholar is that in a field which is purportedly devoted to delight, they
have determined on a course of study and work which will keep them perpetually
miserable. The entire point of an
aesthetic representation is, after all, to give pleasure to its readers. Whether or not it is also to contain some
elements of truth is disputed. I myself
would argue that a great
deal of the pleasure is in seeing the truth—in seeing that the way this
character acts in this moment is eminently true to life, in the sense that that
sort of man would indeed act in just that way in that sort of moment. But whether the pleasure comes from the truth
of a depiction or from something else or some combination of things, pleasure
is at the heart of reading, and at the heart of creating an object to be read.
It is odd, then, that those who
are professionally dedicated to the study of things designed to give delight
are so adamantly determined not to enjoy themselves. It is odd that they should choose to attach
themselves to works which are so morally iniquitous as to anger them.
But then again, there are a great
many desiderata that other people enjoy which I, in my saner moments, regard as
odd: power, heels from Prada, and hang-gliding, to name but a few. But there are darker moments when the appeal
of being angry, really, righteously angry at something, and being known to be
angry at it, and respected for it, does appeal to me. There are also moments when the idea of standing
on four-inch calf enhancers sounds exciting, not to say daring. I gave my heels to Goodwill a long time ago;
I have yet to eradicate the remains of empty righteous indignation from my
life. Probably the job of doing so will
go on until my life is over.
But in the meantime, someone
somewhere is writing an essay about how T.S. Eliot or Dickens or Milton or
Shakespeare is evil, and they are angry.
I can only hope that, on some level, they’re enjoying it.
“It is consequently my
degrading duty to serve this upstart as
First Lord of the
Treasury, Lord Chief Justice, Commander-in-Chief,
Lord High Admiral,
Master of the Buckhounds, Groom of the Back Stairs,
Archbishop of Titipu,
and Lord Mayor, both acting and elect, all rolled into one.
And at a salary! A Pooh-Bah paid for his services!
I a salaried
minion! But I do it! It revolts me, but I do it!”
No comments:
Post a Comment